Book Review of Samuel Lebens, A Guide for the Jewish Undecided: A Philosopher Makes the Case for Orthodox Judaism (New Milford: Koren Publishers Jerusalem, 2022).
“If rabbinic
Judaism has anything to say across its borders, it lies in how the
voice of religion might be authoritative without being authoritarian,
unifying without ceasing to be pluralist, and rational without lacking
passion.”
-Rabbi Lord Jonathan Sacks, Zt”l[1]
Rabbi Dr. Samuel Lebens concluded his
most recent book by stating: “For the person rooted in the Jewish
community, reality is calibrated such that the only reasonable course of
action is to commit oneself to live by and continue to shape the
unfolding Torah from Sinai.”[2] This claim, if true, has the potential to revolutionize Jewish discourse and pedagogy for the better.[3]
Lebens frames his argument as
“Pascalberg’s wager,” a Jewish alternative to “Pascal’s wager”: If God
exists and wants Jews to be Orthodox, then Jews can only receive eternal
reward if they are observant of Halakhah. If, however, it turns out
that God does not exist or does not care about human actions, then
nothing is lost by living such a life.
Importantly, this wager addresses only those who already cherish Judaism.[4]
In Lebens’s words, “Pascalberg’s audience are what we might call the
Jewish undecided. They are certainly Jews, and they are committed to
their identity. But they’re undecided about how religiously observant
they should be; or at least, they’re open to reassessing how religiously
observant they should be.”[5]
For such an audience, Lebens claims, the only thinkable options are to
commit to being a religious Jew or to live as a Jew who is not
religious. All other options are what he calls “unthinkable” in that
they will not be factored into the practical deliberations of a person
who already feels rooted in the Jewish community.[6]
It should be noted upfront, though, that
being a religious Jew and being an Orthodox Jew are not necessarily the
same. Other denominations of Judaism also consider themselves
religious.[7] Lebens must, then, do extra work to demonstrate a “case for Orthodox Judaism,” as the Guide’s subtitle promises.
Unfortunately, Lebens provides no
working definition of Orthodoxy in this book. Elsewhere, Lebens defines
it as the sum of three propositions, based on R. Yosef Albo’s Sefer Ha-Ikkarim: One God created the world, revealed the Torah, and exercises divine providence.[8]
This definition is quite broad and allows for a very big tent of
Orthodoxy. Such a move, however, comes with problems that will be
discussed below.
Regardless, what is the threshold of confidence needed to embrace Orthodoxy? Lebens writes:
If there is a 50
percent chance that God exists, and a 50 percent chance, if He exists,
that He wants Jews to observe Jewish law, then there is a 25 percent
chance that both claims are true together. And if there is a 25 percent
chance that God exists and that God wants Jews to keep Jewish law, and especially if the odds are better
than that, as I think them to be, then it would be crazy for
Pascalberg’s audience not to commit to a life of devout religious
observance – however hard that may be.[9]
The minimal threshold, then, is
demonstrating at least a 50% chance that God exists and another 50%
chance that, if He exists, He wants Jews to be observant of Halakhah. If
both are provided, then a 25% total chance should be enough to warrant
commitment to Orthodoxy by the Jewish undecided since they are already
pragmatically predisposed to some form of Judaism. Though Lebens notes
that the wager would still be effective even if one ends up with
considerably lower credence, he assumes that “if you’ve taken
Pascalberg’s wager, on the basis of this book’s argument… your
confidence in the most fundamental principles of Judaism must be around
25 percent (or more).”[10]
Therefore, 25% total credence is the magic number that this review will
measure toward. While there is perhaps room to critique the view that
pragmatic concerns ought to influence one’s epistemic judgment, this
review will work within Lebens’s assumptions, as laid out above.[11]
Is there at least a 50% chance that God
exists? Lebens defines God as “at least this: a supremely good and
intelligent agent, powerful enough to bring this universe into being,
and to govern its evolution, in accordance with Its will.”[12]
God, then, must minimally possess a mind, a moral capacity, and the
ability to create the universe. Lebens’s first case for this sort of
being is the sheer unlikeliness of life developing without a guiding
hand and how that universe seems to be fine-tuned for the development of
intelligent life.[13]
Of course, this argument does not
automatically prove God. Scientists may posit, for example, that we
exist within a multiverse in which most other universes were not as
lucky. Lebens rejects this idea since it replaces one unobservable God
with an infinite number of equally unobservable universes.[14]
Does this really render God more plausible than a multiverse though?
Naturalists may respond that the only theories that can be taken
seriously are ones that are testable or follow from theories that are.
Sean Carroll, for example, writes that “the multiverse wasn’t invented
because people thought it was a cool idea; it was forced on us by our
best efforts to understand the portion of the universe that we do see”[15]
(emphasis added). Ultimately, “some physicists would put the chances
[of a multiverse] at nearly certain, others at practically zero. Perhaps
it’s fifty-fifty… What matters is that there is a simple, robust
mechanism under which naturalism can be perfectly compatible with the
existence of life, even if the life turns out to be extremely sensitive
to the precise values of the physical parameters characterizing our
environment.”[16]
The above case, however, is far from the
only one that Lebens brings in defense of theism’s plausibility. A full
chapter is dedicated to exploring nearly two dozen arguments for theism
from Alvin Plantinga, perhaps the world’s most renowned Christian
analytic philosopher.[17]
While Lebens acknowledges that no individual argument can ultimately
prove the existence of God, they “can serve, cumulatively, as an
important source of consideration for weighing up how likely – or
plausible – it is that He does.”[18]
Lebens then dedicates a chapter to
examining personal religious experience. We generally assume that our
experiences correspond to something real, so if you have ever had the
experience of an encounter with the divine, you should take it
seriously. Indeed, Jerome (Yehuda) Gellman argues that “the phenomenon
of mystical experiences of God provides initial evidential sufficiency
for the conclusion that human beings at least sometimes genuinely
experience God” in the same way that our personal experience of anything
provides initial reason to believe it, unless proven otherwise.[19]
The atheist, though, can respond that
they have no reason to change how they believe on the basis of another’s
description. Such experiences can also come from many stimuli, and they
do not necessarily have to be the result of an encounter with the
divine. Gellman himself confirms that “the Argument from Perception [of
religious experience] is not universally rationally compelling, in the
sense of rationally obligating all who would ponder it.”[20]
Such an experience may be sufficient for the one who actually perceives
it, but it need not influence one who does not share it. They can, of
course, choose to assign weight based on the descriptions of others or
based on the sheer amount of people who seem to share a common
experience of the divine if they feel so compelled.
While none of the arguments presented by
Lebens definitively prove God’s existence, he notes that “what speaks
most strongly in favor of God’s existence is the stunning ability of
this one simple hypothesis… to make sense of science itself, and
mathematics, and philosophy, and value. When one simple posit can explain so much, you’ve got a very good reason to endorse it.”[21]
One can perhaps conclude like Graham Oppy that “theism and non-theism
are both reasonable responses to the evidence that people have.”[22] The atheist has a reply for each argument, but the theist remains on firm footing.
Lebens’s case for Orthodoxy, however, is
less smooth. His personal reasoning is that “it seems very likely (on
the assumption that [God] exists) that there was some sort of massive
revelation to the Jewish people, quite unparalleled in global history:
the revelation at Mount Sinai.”[23]
But what reason do the Jewish undecided have to believe in such a
revelation? Lebens’s main argument is the “Jumbled Kuzari Principle,”
championed by Tyron Goldschmidt, which posits:
A tradition is
likely true if it is (1) accepted by a nation; describes (2) a national
experience of a previous generation of that nation; which (3) would be
expected to create a continuous national memory until the tradition is
in place;[24]
is (4) insulting to that nation [e.g., it calls them stiff-necked and
lists their sins]; and (5) makes universal, difficult and severe demands
on that nation.[25]
Lebens notes that “adding so many
clauses to the principle makes it look ad hoc, as if it has been reverse
engineered to bring people to believe in the biblical story of the
Exodus and the revelation at Sinai” but also claims that “each clause of
Goldschmidt’s version of the principle, when seen in action,
contributes something compelling.”[26]
The issue with Lebens’s presentation of Goldshmidt’s argument, however,
is that it calls for a thought experiment to bolster its claim rather
than providing clear examples of stories that match the five criteria
which we also know to be historically accurate and cases of proven myths
not meeting those criteria. Additionally, while Goldshmidt’s argument
may be enough to warrant belief in the divinity of the Torah, Lebens
presents no argument to get from there to the Talmud and broader
rabbinic tradition. The reader is therefore left unsure of how much
credence to actually assign based on the argument alone.
Even then, the 50% chance of a revelation
is only half the battle. Lebens still has to show that the Torah, and
its Orthodox interpretation, authentically represents it. He does so by
noting:
If an all-knowing God exists and orchestrated the Sinai event, then He foresaw
the literature, ritual, and law that would come tumbling into being as a
result of the Jewish experience at Sinai. And yet, God chose to
initiate the experience.
Consequently, I would argue that we
should view the theophany at Sinai as something like a divine stamp of
approval for the religious tradition that grew out of it.[27]
Lebens notes that such an approach “ignores the fact that many competing
traditions can be described as tumbling out of that one event.
Presumably, God can’t have been endorsing them all – given their
incompatibility.”[28] How, then, can he argue specifically for Orthodoxy?
Lebens responds by limiting the scope of
God’s approval: “Much of the time, God might not mind which particular
route, within the parameters of Jewish law, is chosen by the process of
rabbinic debate; God simply endorses the process.”[29]
At any time, in any generation, engagement with Jewish texts can lead
to their own set of rituals, cultural expectations, and the like within
the communities most committed to studying them and implementing the
practices learned therefrom. As long as interpretation stays tied to the
source texts, which had God’s initial approval, that which is learned
out from them can also have been said to be approved by God. Most forms
of non-Orthodox Judaism, in rejecting so many of those source texts and
the lessons contained in them, then, are out of the running as
candidates for divine approval. As Lebens points out, “If you’re looking
for a community whose membership defines itself in terms of commitment to the Jewish textual tradition, you’re likely to find only Orthodox candidates.”[30] We will see below, however, that this is not necessarily true.
But it’s also not easy to join an
Orthodox community given the appearance of anti-progressivism,
anti-intellectualism, elitism, sexism, and homophobia that many
perceive. Right or wrong, this impression leads to Orthodoxy being seen
as an intuitively unethical choice for many. Even convinced of the
viability of revelation, then, Orthodoxy may be a hard sell for the
Jewish undecided.
This, however, is not a problem for
Lebens. For him, God need not be responsible for every decision that the
Orthodox community makes. God endorsed the general process of religious
development, not every particular twist and turn along the way.
Halakhah, though binding as part of a divine process, is an
approximation of God’s will rather than a reflection of it.[31]
Over time, Orthodox communities may develop in a different direction.
If one does not have the patience to wait, though, Lebens advocates
picking a sect that is more in line with their moral intuition:
If some pockets of Orthodoxy are unthinkable
to you, because of the things that they stand for, and because of the
ways in which they understand the tradition, then you might want to find
that cross section of the Jewish community that (1) defines itself in
terms of commitment to the Jewish textual tradition, but which also
(2) embodies as much ethical sensitivity, and worldliness, as can be
rendered consistent with that commitment to the Jewish textual
tradition.[32]
This however, need not lead one to
Orthodoxy. While for Lebens “a modern Orthodoxy is the safest bet, since
– to my ethical constitution – certain forms of ultra-Orthodoxy are
simply unthinkable,”[33]
others may rule out even Modern Orthodoxy due to the same sort of
concerns. As long as the community one joins meets Lebens’s criteria,
why does it need to be Orthodox at all?
Hadar, for example, defines itself by its staunch commitment to “Torah, Avodah, and Hesed” in a fully egalitarian environment. Indeed, Rabbi Yitz Greenberg publicly posted on Facebook
that “Hadar is my fantasy of the future modern Orthodox community…
committed to Torah learning and full observance of mitzvot. At the same
time, the principle of egalitarianism was so precious and important that
they practiced it in the here and now, not in a distant future.”
Furthermore, the Conservative Movement’s Statement of Principles
notes that Halakhah “is an indispensable element of a traditional
Judaism,” and Rabbi David Golinkin has written that “commitment to the
centrality of the halakhah has been a hallmark of Conservative Judaism”[34] for theocentric, ethnocentric, and anthropocentric reasons.[35]
While one may argue that these
communities do not practice what they preach in this regard, it is
important to note that Lebens’s criteria is that a community “defines itself in terms of commitment to the Jewish textual tradition,”[36]
not that it always lives as such. If one is content being part of an
observant minority, they can do so while still fitting within Lebens’s
criteria for Orthodoxy, despite themselves being part of many different
non-Orthodox streams of Judaism. Many of those streams, no doubt, even
believe that God would prefer people join them than be Orthodox!
It is hard, then, for this approach to
guarantee staying within Orthodoxy, especially since Lebens himself
offers no practical definition of what Orthodox Judaism ought to look
like outside of the abovementioned criteria. In a book with the subtitle
“A Philosopher Makes the Case for Orthodox Judaism,” this is a glaring
omission and major challenge to the premise.[37]
Lebens seems to be aware of this critique, since he acknowledges in The Principles of Judaism that “Orthodoxy can only coherently claim that the warrant of Sinai flows most forcefully
in the direction of Orthodoxy. But this is neither to say that
Orthodoxy has a monopoly on religious truth, nor is it to say that
Orthodoxy has no religious lessons to learn from other Jewish
movements.”[38]
Lebens even argues that the existence of other Jewish denominations
(and, for that matter, other religions) are themselves integral for
Torah to properly unfold:
… Many factors play a
role in bringing the Torah closer to its heavenly paradigm. Social and
political movements, other religions, and more directly, non-Orthodox
denominations within the Jewish world, all play a role in awakening
certain sensitivities and attitudes within the Orthodox community.
Liberal segments of that community agitate for change within the
halakha. Conservative elements within the same community resist any
change. The legal traditions themselves create obstacles to some
changes, whilst being more amenable to other changes. The changes and
evolutions that make it through this process can claim to be an echo of
Sinai.[39]
Under that assumption, one can easily
argue that God wants them to be part of the element advocating for
change. In doing so, whether on the liberal extreme of Orthodoxy or as a
member of a competing denomination that still views Torah as divine,
they can argue with total intellectual honesty that they are continuing
the Sinai tradition under Lebens’s assumptions. As Benjamin Ish-Shalom
wrote, “When every view and idea are seen as modes of revelation,
skepticism and relativism become transformed into certainty regarding
the truth value of any particular view, on the condition that awareness
of its relative status within the framework of the all-inclusive unity
is preserved.”[40]
Lebens’s second argument, then, is
mixed. If one presupposes the existence of God, there is some degree of
plausibility that He also revealed Himself to the Jewish people. But
does it reach the 50% threshold? That’s harder to measure and largely
depends on how much weight one assigns Goldshmidt’s Jumbled Kuzari
Principle. If one is convinced by it, then the likelihood may very well
be over 90%. But if one finds it lacking, the chance may be more like
20% or 30% at most. It’s clear, then, that only those members of the
Jewish undecided who are predisposed to accepting Goldshmidt’s argument
will have sufficient credence to embrace observance. Though it remains
unclear why one who accepts Lebens’s argument should specifically be
Orthodox.[41]
Since Lebens himself does not expect
anyone to take the wager with less than 25% credence, it can be assumed
that the arguments formulated in his book will not convince all of the Jewish undecided to become Orthodox, or observant in general.[42]
But even for those who reached 25% credence, does it really make sense
to become observant on the basis of such a wager? Lebens notes in his
2022 book, Philosophy of Religion: The Basics,
that allowing one to accept the claims of their current religion with
minimal credence as long as there is no extreme counter-evidence can
apply to any religion.[43]
Should a Jew really be willing to accept Orthodoxy on the basis that we
need “better evidence for the falsehood of Judaism than we do for its
truth” and that “all the evidence we really need is evidence sufficient
to show that Judaism isn’t obviously false”[44] if doing so implicitly allows for Evangelicals, Catholics, Mormons, Muslims, and more to be justified in doing the same?
Basing one’s faith on such a bet also
requires responding to several additional objections. Perhaps it is
selfish to base one’s faith on a wager, which effectively turns God into
a means to an end. Lebens responds that obeying God’s commands, even
without 100% certainty that He exists, is not turning God into a means
to an end. It is just obeying what you understand His will to be. God
commanded things with the understanding that following them entailed
costs and benefits, so it is hard to call calculating those factors
avaricious. Additionally, Judaism has a long tradition of encouraging
people to initially do commandments not for their own sake, in order to
eventually perform them for their own sake.
Another objection may claim that
attempting to make yourself believe something despite a lack of
sufficient evidence is inauthentic. One could respond that trying to
force belief may lead to developing true belief over time, though Lebens
relates this approach to “self-hypnosis.” One might also compare this
response to the sunk cost fallacy, which mistakenly assumes that
significant investment in a project automatically justifies its
continuation, even if the project appears to be failing. In other words,
a person would not automatically be justified to continue putting
effort into making themselves believe in the absence of evidence just
because they have already put in a good amount of effort. But Lebens
would respond that this “doesn’t mean that [trying to believe] isn’t the
reasonable and rational thing to do given the potential risks, and
benefits, and the odds in question.”[45]
Despite a lack of clear evidence, then, it may be that the most
rational thing to do is attempt to make yourself believe regardless of
whether the minimal threshold is met.
Unfortunately, this response does not
fully address the situation that many readers will end up in. Even for
those who end up with more than 25% credence, it is far from certain
that the only reasonable course for someone rooted in the
Jewish community is to embrace Orthodox observance. As noted, there are
many ways that one can potentially live as a Jew, each of which sees
themselves as rooted in a divinely inspired textual tradition. If one is
to view Orthodoxy as the only reasonable way to
experience Judaism, they need to have good epistemic reason. 25%
credence may be enough to justify general observance, but not
necessarily within Orthodoxy.
Furthermore, even if one accepts a 25% credence for Orthodoxy, that still allows for 75% against it.[46]
This is a problem since Lebens himself notes that “to the extent that
[the fundamental propositions of Orthodox Judaism] are ill-grounded by
the evidence, and certainly to the extent that they are victim to
counter-evidence, the religion will be less justified.”[47]
This problem is made all the more worrying by the fact that, as Sean
Carroll points out, one of the principles of credential reasoning is
that “evidence that favors one alternative automatically disfavors
others.”[48]
Therefore, the 75% credence that does not support Orthodox Judaism
ought to actively count against their credence in Orthodox Judaism. For
many, this is likely an uneasy concession.
We are left, then, at an odd point.
While there is ample room to demonstrate a 50% credence that God exists,
revelation is a mixed bag. While many will be at least 50% convinced,
others may reject the Jumbled Kuzari Principle to varying degrees.
Furthermore, even those who end up with a 25% or higher total credence
still run the risk of not ending up within Orthodoxy at all. Even those
who do would need to find peace with the idea of resting their
commitment to Orthodox Judaism on a wager that has a significant chance
of not paying off. While this may be a wager that many accept, there
seems to be little reason to assume that Orthodoxy is the only rational option for the Jewish undecided.
Regardless, The Guide for the Jewish Undecided
is a remarkable step forward in a genre that can loosely be described
as internal Jewish apologetics. This in itself is a major accomplishment
since, as Etai Lahav noted in his own review,
Jews in search of high-level analytic philosophical cases for theism
could only find affordable and accessible works by Christian authors
until now.
Lebens makes a strong, passionate,
modest, and non-coercive case that does not shy away from difficult
questions or sacrifice rigorous philosophy on the altar of popular
spirituality. As an argument for commitment to Halakhah in general, it
is one of the strongest yet made. In the spirit of Rabbi Sacks, his
argument is truly “authoritative without being authoritarian, unifying
without ceasing to be pluralist, and rational without lacking passion.”
While it may not be fully convincing to some, it will no doubt
strengthen and guide many on the path toward thinking actively about
their Jewish identities and the place of Halakhah therein.
https://thelehrhaus.com/commentary/the-odds-of-orthodoxy/?utm_source=Lehrhaus+Readers&utm_campaign=a8e6530ffc-Lehrhaus+Latest+152_COPY_01&utm_medium=email&utm_term=0_5effc5ad09-a8e6530ffc-19243567&mc_cid=a8e6530ffc&mc_eid=a570c54e7f